(intro music) I'm Chris Surprenant, and I teach in the department of philosophy at
the University of New Orleans. This video is part of my series
on human well-being and the good life, and it examines
Immanuel Kant's account of well-being in his moral, political, and
religious writings. For Kant, the highest good for human beings is attaining both complete
virtue and happiness at the same time. But not only is there no necessary
connection between the two, frequently it is the case that doing what is right is in opposition to doing what
would make us happy. Of these two components of the highest
good, Kant's focus in his moral and political writings is on virtue and what individuals must do to cultivate
a virtuous character. For Kant, virtue is the strength
possessed by individuals to resist bodily inclinations and do what is right simply because it
is the right thing to do. This capacity for virtue is unique to
human beings, because human wills are affected, but not determined,
by bodily desires. This characteristic places
our wills between those of non-rational animals, whose wills are determined by bodily desires, and those of divine beings, whose wills
are determined by reason. Kant claims that the true vocation
of human reason is not to help us to become happy, but rather to make us worthy of happiness by assisting
us in becoming virtuous. Kant closely associates morality,
reason, and freedom. One necessary condition of morally praiseworthy actions is that
they are performed freely. But here, Kant's understanding
of freedom may be a bit different than what we are used to. An individual's action is free if his own reason generated the maxim, or principle,
from which that action was performed. That means that if an individual
was motivated by a bodily desire, like hunger or lust, or he was
coerced or habituated into adopting certain principles, then his actions are not free and he would not
be morally praiseworthy, even if he did the right thing. But to be morally praiseworthy,
it is not enough simply to adopt principles
of action freely. They must be the right principles, or ones that are consistent
with the moral law. Kant connects the moral law directly with reason as well, and he argues
that reason dictates that individuals should "act only in accordance
with that maxim which you can "at the same time will that it
can become a universal law." This, for Kant, is the Categorical
Imperative, and all principles of action can be tested against
the categorical imperative to see if they pass, are
consistent with the demands of morality and can be acted
on, or fail, and should be discarded. The challenge for the virtuous person is
two-fold. Not only must he developed his reasons, so that he can identify what principles
are consistent with the categorical imperative, but he must also
act on those appropriate principles. Kant claims that this development of reason
comes about through education, and as a result, can occur only for an individual
who is a member of a civil community. Living in civil society has the added
benefit of helping to secure the external conditions necessary for
an individual to become virtuous. An individual who lives in constant
fear of sudden and violent death, or is starving and does not know
where his next meal will come from, cannot act virtuously, because he lacks
the necessary degree of external freedom. After an individual has developed the
appropriate degree of reason to identify principles upon which he should act, the last step is actually acting
on those principles. Here, Kant introduces the
concept of self-respect argues that the motivation to act appropriately must be internal, and
claims that the greatest punishment for bad behavior is that an individual feels worthless and contemptible
in his own eyes. The virtuous person, therefore, possesses
the strength and self-respect to not given in to bodily
inclinations, adopts good principles of action freely, and then
acts on these good principles. But virtue is only half
of the highest good. The other half is happiness,
and Kant's religious writings give us insight into how he believes
an individual can hope to become both virtuous and happy, even though it appears as if
these two ends are in tension. His solution is that attaining
the highest good is possible only if there is a supreme creator who is able to guarantee the coexistence
of virtue and happiness. Since we ought to realize the highest
good, that we ought to realize it implies that we can realize it, and that we can
realize it is possible only if God exists and can unite
virtue and happiness. It is reasonable to have faith in the existence of a supreme creator. Whether or not we buy Kant's argument for how virtue and happiness get united,
his understanding of the highest good for human beings is connected to our nature
of being both rational and sensible. Reason, which is developed by living in
civil society, allows us both to generate the moral law and to determine which principles of the action are consistent with it. The strength to set aside our desires
and act on these principles comes from within as well. Subtitles by the Amara.org community