Main content
Wireless Philosophy
Course: Wireless Philosophy > Unit 4
Lesson 2: Early modern- Early Modern: Locke on Personal Identity, Part 1
- Early Modern: Locke on Personal Identity, Part 2
- Early Modern: Locke on Personal Identity, Part 3
- Early Modern: Descartes' Cogito Argument
- Early Modern: Émilie du Châtelet, Part 1
- Early Modern: Émilie du Châtelet, Part 2
- Early Modern: Margaret Cavendish, Part 1
- Early Modern: Margaret Cavendish, Part 2
© 2023 Khan AcademyTerms of usePrivacy PolicyCookie Notice
Early Modern: Émilie du Châtelet, Part 1
In this first of two videos, Andrew Janiak introduces Emilie Du Chatelet, a French philosopher, and her contribution to the debate about the principle of sufficient reason. This video is a part of a series of videos coming from Project Vox (Duke), a project recovering the lost voices of women philosophers.
Speaker: Dr. Andrew Janiak, Creed C. Black Associate Professor of Philosophy, Duke University.
Speaker: Dr. Andrew Janiak, Creed C. Black Associate Professor of Philosophy, Duke University.
Want to join the conversation?
- Shouldn't there be a video about Liebniz before this? Maybe Liebniz and Newton could be done in one go seeing as they were rivals? That would lead into this nicely.(5 votes)
- It seems that they leave out great philosophers so they can promote women in philosophy.(0 votes)
Video transcript
(intro music) This is Andrew Janiak in the philosophy
department at Duke University, where we are leading Project Vox. This is part one of Emilie du Chatelet, a French philosopher who worked in the middle of the eighteenth century. Madame du Chatelet was a member of a
famous aristocratic family in France and was often associated with
the French author Voltaire. For many generations, in fact, scholars saw her primarily in two ways: one, as a collaborator of Voltaire's, rather than a major figure
in her own right; and two, as the most important translator
of Isaac Newton in France. Now in fact she was a collaborator
of Voltaire's for many years, and in fact she did translate, from cover
to cover, Principia Mathematica. However, more recently, scholars
have recognized that Madame du Chatelet actually
was a philosopher of her own. Her main work is called Institutions de
Physique, or Institutions of Physics. One of the most fascinating
aspects of the work is that it actually shows a deep engagement
not only with Newtonian ideas, for example about the nature
of matter, the laws in motion, and the law of universal gravitation,
among other things, but also with the ideas of Leibniz. Now, in France at this time, Leibniz had not had as much influence
as we would expect from his status in the philosophy canon today. And in fact, Madame to Chatelet was
probably the first major thinker in France to take Leibniz's ideas seriously. Christian Wolff, probably the most
important follower of Leibniz's after his death, wrote to
Madame du Chatelet and praised her 1740 book for taking
the ideas of Leibniz seriously. But the great conundrum that
Madame du Chatelet faced was something along the following lines: how do we accept Newtonian
ideas about the physical world and also take seriously the
metaphysical ideas found in Leibniz and Wolff, especially the all-important Principle
of Sufficient Reason. The principal of sufficient reason, or PSR, as philosophy students around
the world will know, tells us that there is a reason for everything to be the way it is, rather
than otherwise. And of course, in 1715 and 1716, Leibniz and the great Netwonian Samuel Clarke held
an extensive debate with one another concerning such issues as how the principle of sufficient reason
should be interpreted. As a result of the influence of the
Leibniz-Clarke correspondence, most philosophers in Europe
believed, at that time, that one had to choose either
a Leibnizian point of view on philosophy, which would center on his interpretation of the principle
of sufficient reason; or a more Newtonian-influenced view, which would either just eschew the principle of sufficient reason altogether or provide something closer
to Clark's interpretation of it. and what is unique about
Madame du Chatelet, in the middle of the eighteenth century, is that she rejected this presupposition. She believed one could be influenced
both by Leibniz and by Newton, without choosing either side. Subtitles by the Amara.org community