Main content
Wireless Philosophy
Ancient: Epicurus’ Cure for Unhappiness
In this video, Monte discusses the “tetrapharmakos” or “four-part remedy” developed by the ancient Greek philosopher Epicurus (341-270 BC) and his followers to treat unhappiness and anxiety. The tetrapharmakos consists of four maxims which encapsulate the Epicurean outlook on god, life, death, pleasure, and pain. The maxims can be meditated upon in order to alleviate worries and concerns that continue to plague us as much as they did the ancients.
Speaker: Dr. Monte Ransome Johnson, Associate Professor, University of California, San Diego. Created by Gaurav Vazirani.
Speaker: Dr. Monte Ransome Johnson, Associate Professor, University of California, San Diego. Created by Gaurav Vazirani.
Want to join the conversation?
- How does the second maxim deal with the possibility of someone (cough, me, cough) being absolutely terrified of not existing?(13 votes)
- Good question. Though I don't have any answer for your problem, I can feel and share your anxious. Sometimes in my life, I deeply think about death and guess what: I am afraid of not opening my eyes some days, of not perceiving anything anymore. At those moments, I truly wish that a random God would suddenly appear and talk to me: "Never fear! There is an afterlife in which you will be wandering around for eternity!"
Well, guess we treasure our souls (not the bodies) so much, heh?(16 votes)
- So, in other words, to use a nerd reference, Epicureanism is like living like a hobbit. Just enjoy the simple pleasure of smoking tobacco, tea, and cakes, and care not for the world outside the shire.(7 votes)
- A bit off-topic question: If the first maxim of tetrapharmakos clearly said "Don't be afraid of God!" or I should say "Don't be afraid of God's punishments!" 2000+ years ago, how could Catholic Church gain power through time and enforce their rules on people, e.g. Galileo's affair?(4 votes)
- Your question is incredibly broad, but the short answer is that Epicureanism was not as popular amongst both intellectuals and the general public as other traditions. Additionally, it declined as Neo-Platonism gained popularity. Neo-Platonism became the dominant philosophical tradition and Christianity eventually spread into philosophy. The philosopher Boethius was the last important heathen philosopher of late antiquity, and he was executed in about 524 AD.
The rise of Christianity was greatly helped by the roman emperor Theodosius making it the official state church.(6 votes)
- Although things like fame and political power are "unnatural and unnecessary desires" they lead to social status and control which make the "natural desires" even easier to obtain(3 votes)
- However, because fame and status make it easier to acquire the "natural desires," these then have a tendency to accumulate, since we really don't need that much to survive. Once they do accumulate, then others will see this as an opportunity to take them from you, in order for them to achieve their own desires. This then, puts you at risk of losing your life, because you desire to protect your stockpile of things that fulfill the "natural desires."(6 votes)
- "Terrible things in life are easy to endure".
This reminded me of something I read Nietzsche wrote: “The thought of suicide is a great consolation: by means of it one gets through many a dark night.”
I know almost nothing about Philosophy, but is Nietzsche in some way influenced by Epicurianism?(4 votes) - The true God is to be feared greatly!
I personally fear death, because God is definitely real and will judge you for your sin!(3 votes) - When Monte Johnson mentioned atthat "this" was the character of a hedonistic philosopher, I am confused as to whom/what he was referring. Was Epicurus so fervent about adhering to his own principles of minimalism that he was a hedonism in respect to his intellect by trying to get the most out of life by rationing his intake and savoring the tiny things he did get, or was the part about indulging in ice cream and trying to maintain satisfaction level after trying all the flavors in different variations a hedonistic philosophy? Was he possibly being ambiguous and broaching that perhaps Epicurus was being too stingy, but still also in fact truly referring to the ice cream example? 8:05
...
Is it the fact that he willed himself to perform this act of enjoyment rather than letting his natural instincts satiate his taste for cheese without forcing himself to ration? ...He used his intellect to say this is optimum satiety?(3 votes) - So if Epicurus took a positive spin on life, did he create euphemisms?(3 votes)
- A little off topic but, what is the difference between philosophy and psychology?(2 votes)
- Philosophy is the study of thinking or greek, "The love of Wisdom". But phycology is the study of the mind and how it works. Ex. decision making parts of your brain. If you want to know more about it, go on to youtube and search up crashcourse. It is a page with almost all topics from study of games to, yes you guesses right, philosophy and phycology.(2 votes)
- I have an issue with the 3rd maxim and I was wondering how others view this.
Take the basic need for food/water and shelter. These are no longer freely available in modern day society, through privatization of basically everything, from the water we drink to the ground we stand on.
For example, I cant simply walk into the woods, pick a nice spot and build myself a hut to call home. I could turn my garden into a mini-farm but to do so you need to invest quite a lot and I wouldn't dare say it is easy to acquire. Also, I do not think I need to elaborate on how many examples there are of people finding it quite difficult to obtain food and shelter on a regular, secure basis. The fascination with the illusive idea of wealth seems to fuel the substantial problems that poverty causes. I.e. the basic things we need become difficult to acquire.
Does this theory (at least concerning this 3rd maxim) still hold up in modern day society? What is your view?(2 votes)
Video transcript
(intro music) Hi, my name is Monte Johnson. I teach philosophy at the
University of California, San Diego, and today I want
to talk about Epicureanism's four-part cure for unhappiness,
the Tetrapharmakos. God is nothing to fear, death is nothing to worry about, it is easy to acquire
the good things in life, and it is easy to endure
the terrible things. These four maxims are the
first four capital doctrines of Epicureanism, collectively
known as the "Tetrapharmakos." "Tetrapharmakos" literally
means "four-part remedy," or "cure." The term originally referred
to a medical concoction of four drugs, but the
Epicureans mean by it the encapsulation of their
philosophy in a formula of four easily digestible
maxims that one can meditate on in order to relieve anxiety, much like modern cognitive
behavioral therapy. As Epicurus says, "Meditate
on these ideas day and night, "and the ones related to
them, both alone and with "someone like yourself,
and you will never be badly "disturbed, whether awake or dreaming." In order to see how the
maxims might contribute to our tranquility, let's briefly expand on each part of the tetrapharmakos. First, God is not to be feared. Traditional religion presents
us with terrifying visions of superpowerful gods, such
as Zeus with his thunderbolts, or Poseidon who, with a
rattle of his trident, can cause earthquakes and storms. The perceived need to mollify
such gods with sacrifices is the source of much
distress, worry, and expense, and has had terrible consequences. But for both scientific and
theological reasons, the divine should not be thought to be
the cause of natural disasters. Epicurus, in his treatise on
nature, gave a comprehensive account of the universe and its origin, including living things and human beings. This account removed
from natural philosophy the need for any appeal
to God as a creator or maintainer or end of
nature and natural phenomena. Epicurus says that if we consider
God to be an invulnerable and happy living thing,
then God must be completely unbothered and unworried by human affairs, and unaffected by either
anger or pity, which are kinds of suffering incompatible
with divine perfection. It is, in fact, impious,
according to Epicurus, to represent God as inflicting
punishment on human beings, whether through natural
disasters or in the afterlife, and it is unholy to
sacrifice human goods as if we could possibly
influence or benefit a god. Second, death is nothing
to be worried about. In connection with the first
maxim, there is no need to worry that God will
punish you after death. Furthermore, our natural
science tells us that when our body breaks down, the
living thing ceases to exist. There is no immaterial soul that can be tormented or rewarded in the afterlife. Death is nothing to us, for it can affect neither the living nor the dead. It cannot affect you when you're living, because then you're not dead yet, and it cannot affect you when you're dead, because then you don't exist anymore. The ancient fear of dwelling
for eternity in the darkness of subterranean Hades is baseless, as is the medieval worry
about being tortured in Hell. As for lamenting the loss
of everything you could have experienced had you died
later, you need not worry about that any more than
you worry about everything you could have experienced in
the time before you were born. The time before you were born
and the time after you die are equal, but there is no
more reason to regret that you will not be alive in the
distant future than there is to regret that you were not
alive in the distant past. In fact, it is comforting to
realize that everything in life is limited, and that
beyond a certain point, all striving and suffering
necessarily ends. And once one removes the
fear of death and longing for more life, almost all
other fears disappear, and we become free to
enjoy the lifetime we have. This brings us to the third
maxim of tetrapharmakos: the good things in life
are easy to acquire. When we consider the things
we want, it is comforting to realize that our true needs
are limited and fairly easily available from nature, and
that the things that are difficult to obtain, we just don't need. Air is available for our
breath, water for our thirst, fire for warmth, and earth
for ground to stand on. The minerals, plants, and animals supply our needs for shelter and sustenance. There are plenty of people
around to become our friends. When we realize that we
have enough, not just to survive, but to
alleviate most of our pain, we necessarily become
relieved and tranquil. True relaxation and
happiness becomes possible. We can focus not only on
survival, but on a deeper, more aesthetic appreciation
of the universe that seeks to understand the
nature of things, not only to provide what we need
and to eliminate our fears about the divine and
about death, but simply to be amazed at its beauty and sublimity. Epicurus describes this
state as "god-like" because when we are in it, we are
invulnerable, happy creatures who do not fear nature,
but take delight in it. Now, if the idea that the
good things in life are easily available seems doubtful
to you, consider Epicurus's three-fold division of desires
into those that are natural and necessary, like our
desires for air, water, food, or shelter; those that are
natural but not necessary, like our desires for
expensive food and drink, mansions, or sex; and those
that are neither natural nor necessary, which Epicurus
calls "hollow," or "empty." Desires for fame, riches,
glory, political power, and immortality, common though
they are, are all hollow. Their pursuit causes more
unhappiness than happiness, not only because they are
difficult or impossible to achieve, and so efforts
in this direction are futile and frustrating, but also
because they are unlimited. Not being related to any
natural need, there is no amount of wealth, influence, or life
extension that will satisfy us and allow us to live a
relaxed, tranquil life. Ease of living comes by
appreciating just how little we need to be happy or flourish,
and how abundant nature seems to be in supplying our needs. All of our pleasures boil
down to just two kinds. On the one hand, there is
the pleasant, agreeable, sweet stimulation that Epicurus
calls "kinetic pleasure," and on the other hand,
the tranquil, satisfied, self-sufficient, and self-assured
state that comes when all pain is relieved, which Epicurus
calls "static pleasure." Both kinds are good, but
both are naturally limited. The most intense kinetic pleasures come from satisfying our natural needs. Thus, drinking when we're
thirsty, eating when we're hungry, warming up when we're cold. Once these natural and
necessary desires are satisfied, we reach the more stable
condition of static pleasure. At this point we cannot
increase our pleasure any more, but can only vary it. I can have either chocolate
or vanilla ice cream, or I can have both, but
beyond a certain point, eating ice cream will not be
any more enjoyable for me, nor will eating any other food. When one is very thirsty,
simple water is what one most desires, and simple
foods when one is most hungry. Accustoming oneself to
enjoying simpler pleasures makes the enjoyment of
luxuries all that much more enjoyable when windfalls
happen to come along. That is why Epicurus, who
practically lived on bread and water, asked to be brought
a pot of cheese every once in a while, so that he
could, as he put it, "indulge." This is the character of
the hedonistic philosopher who devoted his life to pleasure. Epicurus does not need
to go to the trouble of always having a pot of
cheese with every meal, and as a general rule, one
is better off eliminating a desire, rather than working
too hard to satisfy it. In fact, it is often necessary
to forgo one pleasure in order to enjoy a
greater pleasure later, just as it is often necessary
to undergo some pain in order to avoid a greater pain later. That brings us to the fourth and final maxim of the tetrapharmakos: the terrible things in
life are easy to endure. Acute pain, although sharp, is short. Chronic pain, although
long-lasting, is dull. If pain ever becomes too
intense for too long, there's always the option of
ending life, at which point no harm can come to us whatsoever. Once again, we should
appreciate and be relieved at how the limits of
nature have benefited us, and we should derive
tranquility from this. And when this appreciation
takes an intellectual form of research and philosophical discussion, it offers rewards that more
than offset and compensate for life's annoyances, pains, and sorrows. Even though Epicurus was
suffering from painful kidney stones at the end of his
life, he wrote to his friend Idomeneus, "These pains I
have offset with the joy "I feel when I recall our
philosophical conversations." Subtitles by the Amara.org community